Call
no man happy until you know the nature of his death. — Herodotus,
Clio, I, 32.
But
we must add ‘in a complete life’. For one swallow does not make
a summer, nor does one day; and so too one day, or a short time, does
not make a man blessed and happy. – Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics.
This is a follow up to my post: Wisdom, Virtue, and Happiness.
In
this post, we revisit the moral and ethical elements of the classical
conception of eudaemonia and explore the implications of happiness as
the final cause of our lives. An examination of the moral or ethical
definitions of happiness is important because the psychological
definitions of happiness as desire and fulfillment are often
fleeting, vague, and temporal. Further, our desires are often
misplaced and we become misguided in a false pursuit of happiness.
Nonetheless, the issue of what constitutes happiness is valid. “Man
wishes to be happy, and only wishes to be happy, and cannot wish not
to be so,” writes Blaise Pascal. On the question of what moves
human desire, John Locke tells us “happiness and that alone.” In
fact, many philosophers—from a variety of perspectives—have made
happiness the primary object of human action (which, by the way,
implies an ethical element). Here I’m thinking of philosophers
such as Aristotle, Aquinas, Locke, or J.S. Mill. Happiness and its
pursuit seems to be a universal quest for humanity and the human
impulse for happiness seems to be intuitively correct. Therefore,
seeking the correct definition of happiness is important for several
reasons. As noted in my previous post, social scientists are able to
talk about the need for human happiness without giving a definition
of it. Statistics mean little if no definition or perhaps a wrong
definition of happiness is given. However, if we can define
happiness correctly, we will have a better understanding of how to
attain it.
Wisdom
is the discovery and understanding of first principles combined with
the virtue of using our knowledge well. In the classical Western
tradition, Eudaemonia is among the first principles in correctly
understanding happiness. It is the idea that happiness as the
highest good of the individual is achieved rationally without the
extremes of excessive repression or inordinate indulgence. Happiness
understood as the harmony and consonancy of a rationally well lived
life will help in understanding why it is thought to be the final end
or purpose in human activity.
In
this sense, happiness is said to be the goal or final end of mankind.
We begin at the end as T.S. Eliot reminds us. In this case, the end
is the purpose or reason for the goal-directed activity that all of
us partake in one way or another. What is the end of human
existence? Happiness. This is why many philosophers have said that
the happy life is one with a good ending. Think of someone who is
suffering with chronic pain or experiencing genuine existential
tragedy in his or her life but is also happy. A play or TV show is
considered a comedy although the characters themselves display a
painful existence and many tragic flaws. Think of the talented
genius, gifted artist, or young entrepreneur whose life is suddenly
cut short in a horrible way. We call this a catastrophe, not
happiness. I think this is one reason Herodotus reminds us to “call
no man happy until you know the nature of his death”. Happiness,
therefore, is seen as the end, purpose, or goal-directed nature of
human existence and what it means to be and become in this temporary
life. It is that which mankind tends toward—as all things tend
toward the fulfillment of their nature.
Understanding
that there is nothing beyond happiness for which humans seek,
Aristotle uses the term happiness as the ultimate good, last end, or
summum bonum (highest good).
“The
chief good,” he writes, “is evidently something final . . . Now
we call that which is in itself worthy of pursuit more final than
that which is worthy of pursuit for the sake of something else, and
that which is never desirable for the sake of something else more
final than the things that are desirable both in themselves and for
the sake of that other thing. Therefore, we call final without
qualification that which is always desirable in itself and never for
the sake of something else. Such a thing, happiness, above all else,
is held to be; for this we choose always for itself and never for the
sake of something else.” (Nicomachean Ethics)
Aristotle
supports his argument that happiness is the final end of human
activity with the notion of self-sufficiency or completeness. It
would make no sense to pursue happiness as a final end if it were
incomplete or something in addition is needed to make it complete.
One would run into an endless regression of desire fulfillment.
Ultimately, the happy life leaves nothing to be desired. As
Aristotle explains:
“The
self-sufficient we now define as that which when isolated makes life
desirable and lacking in nothing; and such we think happiness to be;
and further we think it most desirable of all things, without being
counted as one good thing among others—if it were so counted it
would clearly be made more desirable by the addition of even the
least of goods; for that which is added becomes an excess of goods,
and of goods the greater is always more desirable. Happiness, then,
is something final and self-sufficient, and is the end of action”
(Nicomachean Ethics)
When you ask someone why they do what they do, you will find that happiness is the chief end of human activity. Perhaps you have questioned someone, “why do you work so hard?” They might say, so I can meet the needs of my family and buy things.” But when you drill down and ask why do you want to meet your family’s needs or buy things, you will discover that happiness is the ultimate pursuit. Whatever we do, it is with the end of some good in mind. Happiness understood as the harmony and consonancy of a rationally well-lived life will help guide one in making the right goal directed choices for their life. This is why Aristotle explains that “human good turns out to be activity of soul in accordance with virtue.”
It
is simply impossible to cover the entire range of human happiness in
just two posts. I hope to come back to it again. There is much more
to be discussed such as the function of wisdom and the happy life,
the role of virtue in the pursuit of happiness, and perhaps the
social aspects of happiness as the common good. Nonetheless,
understanding happiness as the primary goal-directed nature of human
existence is the primary first principle one must grasp.
Until
I get to this topic again, I recommend the following for further
reading:
Aristotle’s
Nicomachean Ethics
Aquinas’
section on happiness in his Summa Theologica
Josef
Pieper’s book Happiness and Contemplation
Martin
Seligman’s book Authentic Happiness
Miguel
de Unamuno’s book Tragic Sense of Life
Recent Comments