Metaphysics, Philosophy

Aristotle on “True Truth”

I will get to my explication of Plato soon. In the meantime, I wanted to share one of the most beautiful and inspiring philosophical passages of the Western intellectual tradition. Perhaps I will write about it sometime. Right now, however, I do not want to say anything about it for fear of ruining it. Just enjoy.

It is right also that philosophy should be called knowledge of the truth. For the end of theoretical knowledge is truth, while that of practical knowledge is action (for even if they consider how things are, practical men do not study the eternal, but what is relative and in the present). Now we do not know a truth without its cause; and a thing has a a quality in a higher degree than other things if in virtue of it the similar quality belongs to the other things as well (e.g. fire is the hottest of things; for it is the cause of the heat of all other things); so that that which causes derivative truths to be true is most true. Hence the principles of eternal things must be always most true (for they are not merely sometimes true, nor is there any cause of their being, but they themselves are the cause of the being of other things), so that as each thing is in respect of being, so is it in respect of truth. (Aristotle, Metaphysics, Book II, end of chapter 1)

Metaphysics, Philosophy, Philosophy of Science

Epilogue: A Twenty-First Century Meditation on First-Philosophy

[Note: As July quickly approaches, I will not be making many posts on this blog. I will have my two beautiful daughters with me for the month and much of my time will be spent with my family. These are the times I rediscover that love is the primary matter which holds our family together.]

At any rate, here are some initial and unfinished thoughts regarding physics and metaphysics. The more I delve into the concept of Being, the further I seem to go into the philosophy of science and the existential import of what it means to be and become in this temporal world. I remain impressed by how the classical categories of Western thought (specifically, act and potency, accepted by both neo-Platonists and Aristotelians) hold up and have stood the test of time.

Part two of my essay on Heisenberg’s appeal to Aristotelian metaphysics can be found here.

I probably won’t be able to explicate these further until August, but here are a few rough and undeveloped reflections that came to me when thinking about the intersection of science and the philosophical first principles of reality. Post below if you have anything to add or something which you think needs further discussion.

1. The Copenhagen School interpretation of quantum mechanics seems to indicate that we can say nothing about the properties of an atom or sub-atomic particles. All scientists can do is provide the results of experiments on them. Would it be better to say that the strange behavior of quantum mechanics demonstrates the classical nature of potential waiting to be put into act? Perhaps that is the nature or essence of quantum physics?

2. The mystery of causality. Predictability in the quantum realm may not hold in particular cases. That does not mean, however, that there is no efficient cause or sufficient reason for its action. An efficient cause may be unpredictable but that does not mean it does not exist.

3. The actual world we live in is alive with potentialities from the smallest elements of matter to human individuals. This is what we mean when we speak of “human potential.” Our world is charged with real potentialities, relationships, and interactions between real beings.

4. Many of the early scientists and mathematicians working on quantum phenomena such as Planck, Heisenberg, and Bohr were not strict materialists. Neither were other influential thinkers of the time such as Bergson, Einstein, Whitehead, and Hardy. They all understood that something more is going on in our world than matter, energy, and motion. In other words, they would have rejected the undue and uncritical acceptance of the scientific method as it is applied to every other field of inquiry such as philosophy, history, or the humanities.

5. Perhaps Einstein’s formula regarding the convertibility of matter and energy (Energy = the mass x the speed of light squared), points to Aristotle’s “primary matter”? (It may of itself have no form but must always be structured by some form or essence?)

6. The classic question of the one and many. Heraclitus was only half correct when he stated that all reality is in flux. Our world is not in total or complete flow or chaos. Even Heisenberg’s Indeterminacy Principle is not infinite. There must be something that perdures or there would be no sense of continuity. In this regard, quantum physics point to the classical question of the one and many (which also speaks to the nature of relationships).

7. The great conversation regarding act and potency which was started by Aristotle, accepted by Plotinus, elaborated by Aquinas, and rediscovered by Heisenberg needs to be explored, developed, and integrated for our time. Metaphysics is about recovering the first principles of Being.

Metaphysics, Philosophy, Philosophy of Science

Between Possibility and Reality: Heisenberg’s Appeal to Aristotelian Metaphysics, Part Two

So what do Aristotelian-Thomist notions of act/potency and form/matter have to do with quantum dynamics? In 1975 Werner Heisenberg gave a lecture to German physicists and said, “good science is being unconsciously discarded because of bad philosophy” and sought to correct the situation with his book, Physics and Philosophy. The bad philosophy that Heisenberg wanted to redress was the materialistic, mechanistic, and deterministic view of nature assumed by Enlightenment physicists and philosophers. He specifically appealed to the metaphysics of Aristotle to correct the deterministic view of Newtonian physics. It is important to note at this point that much of Aristotle’s ideas were either thrown out or misinterpreted by early modern philosophers and scientists due to their materialist assumptions. Heisenberg’s appeal to Aristotle’s metaphysics was a bold new move for his day but he realized it made the most sense out the facts as they were presented to him.

So what was Heisenberg getting at when he explained the function of sub-atomic particles in the Aristotelian category of ‘potential’? In his book Physics and Philosophy, he tells us:

“In throwing dice we do not know the fine details of the motion of our hands which determine the fall of the dice and therefore we say that the probability for throwing a special number is just one in six. The probability wave of Bohr, Kramers, Slater, however, meant more that; it meant a tendency for something. It was a quantitative version of the old concept of “potentia” in Aristotelian philosophy. It introduced something standing in the middle between the idea of an event and the actual event, a strange kind of physical reality just in the middle between possibility and reality” (396).

According to Heisenberg, the probability inherent in quantum behavior is potential – a tendency for something. (This might also imply a ‘telos,’ or purpose, but we will not develop that here.) Heisenberg is clearly stating that the many abilities, capacities, possibilities, or dispositional properties a sub-atomic particle has is its potential.

When explaining the unity of matter as energy or universal matter (similar to Aristotle’s ‘prime matter”) Heisenberg says this, “If we compare this situation with the Aristotelian concepts of matter and form, we can say that the matter of Aristotle, which is mere “potentia,” should be compared to our concept of energy, which gets into “actuality” by means of the form, when the elementary particle is created” (440). Here Heisenberg is intuitively correct. Matter is always in potential. Contrary to early modern philosophers such as Descartes and others, matter and form are not so easily thrown out. Matter and form, or as Heisenberg might say, energy as a form of matter are necessary conceptual tools which physicists use to describe the world. Here, it is important to note two things, the first is that potential is not empirical, the second is that potency is not pure chaos.

First, potential is inaccessible to the strict empiricist. No empiricist who believes that all human knowledge is restricted to what can be observed by some sense experience can allow for potency. Why? Because although potency can be observed through act as an effect (in hindsight, so to speak), it can not be directly observed by itself through sense perception. This is why no real scientist is a strict empiricist because they are always appealing to properties, capacities, probabilities, or capabilities of matter, even though potential is never known by itself apart from that which is in act. The second thing to keep in mind is that at the quantum level, the range of probabilities (potential) is not absolutely indeterminable or chaotic. Heisenberg’s uncertainty principle states that the quantum mechanical behavior of sub-atomic particles is not absolutely indeterminate because it can only oscillate between a range of probabilistic values (Silva 638). This is why things correspond to their nature or essence. Potency can only have an effect on a range of possibilities to that which is in act.

Finally, Heisenberg claimed that many of his fellow physicists were coming to the same Aristotelian conclusions, “One might perhaps call it an objective tendency or possibility, a ‘potentia’ in the sense of Aristotelian philosophy. In fact, I believe that the language actually used by physicists when they speak about atomic events produces in their minds similar notions as the concept ‘potentia.’ So the physicists have gradually become accustomed to considering the electronic orbits, etc., not as reality but rather as a kind of ‘potentia’” (447). Heisenberg came to realize that many of his colleagues were beginning to understand the philosophical implications of quantum dynamics in Aristotelian terms. This should not be surprising since reality is the determinate of order and will always reveal its own intractable way of being.

Max Planck, who is considered the father of quantum theory, also held that scientific discoveries ultimately point to a metaphysical reality. Although he did not explicitly use the category of potential, he was very aware of the philosophical implications of quantum mechanics. “As there is a material object behind every sensation, so there is a metaphysical reality behind everything that human experience shows to be real” (97). Potency seems to be the best metaphysical category that explains the mysterious behavior of quantum particles. It certainly cannot explain the entire mystery, for there are still many remaining questions for science to explore but act and potency are viable options that the physicist and metaphysician can use to describe reality. These metaphysical co-principles have stood the test of time and point us to the nature of ultimate reality. In many ways, reality itself points to a metaphysical reality. Plank went on to explain that, “Metaphysical reality does not stand spatially behind what is given in experience, but lies fully within it. … The essential point is that the world of sensation is not the only world which may conceivably exist, but that there is still another world. To be sure, this other world is not directly accessible to us, but its existence is indicated time and time again” (98). The metaphysical co-principles of act/potency and form/matter help us understand what is happening in the physical realm.

From these remarks by Planck and Heisenberg, and through an investigation of the Aristotelian categories of act and potency, we see that reality by its very nature is oriented toward self-expressive action. In classical philosophy, the physical world is seen as “one and many” or “being and becoming” (both are needed to make sense of the world). Potentiality, however, is the category used for explaining the dynamic aspect of life. Nothing in the human, animal, or plant kingdoms can grow, develop, or meet its potential by being static. To stand out of nothing—the very meaning of existence—is to be oriented toward action and is the reason there is a metaphysical basis for reality, even at the atomic level. The Aristotelian categories of act and potency account for the dynamic and changing realities we experience in the world around us. Potency itself is not a strictly empirical phenomenon but is indispensable for accounting for and maintaining the integrity of the empirical data. There are all sorts of non-empirical realities that nature itself points us to—from the smallest sub-atomic particle to human nature itself.

[Special thanks and gratitude go to my friend Dr. Derek Gardner at the University of Arizona for keeping me pointed in the right direction regarding the issues around quantum physics. Without his guidance my ontology would have certainly failed.]

Works Cited

Heisenberg, Werner. Physics and Philosophy. Great Books of the Western World. Vol. 56. Encyclopedia Britannica, Inc., 1999

Planck, Max. Scientific Autobiography and Other Papers. Great Books of the Western World. Vol. 56. Encyclopedia Britannica, Inc., 1999

Silva, Ignacio. “Werner Heisenberg and Thomas Aquinas on Natural Indeterminism.” New Blackfriars, 2013, 635 – 653.

For further reading:

Clarke, Norris. The One and The Many: A Contemporary Thomistic Metaphysics. University of Notre Dame, 2001.

Goetz, Stewart and Charles Taliaferro. Naturalism. Wm. B. Eerdmans Publishing, 2008.

Trigg, Roger. Beyond Matter: Why Science Needs Metaphysics. Templeton Press, 2015.

Moreland, J.P. Scientism and Secularism: Learning to Respond to a Dangerous Ideology. Crossway, 2018.

Ethics, Happiness, Philosophy

Wisdom, Virtue, and Happiness: A Reflection on Eudaemonia

True happiness flows from the possession of wisdom and virtue and not from the possession of external goods. – Aristotle, Politics

I promise I will get back to explicating Aristotle’s understanding of metaphysics as the love of wisdom. However, I recently attended a lecture by Dr. Arthur Brooks (former president of the American Enterprise Institute and Professor of Public Leadership at the Harvard Kennedy School) on the topic of happiness. Dr. Brooks beautifully and elegantly laid out the significant factors that aided and developed human happiness. As a sociologist, he presented his case with support from studies and statistics and laid out the science of human happiness. Further, Dr. Brooks explained the elements that go into a life of deep and long-lasting happiness. It was a well-attended lecture and Dr. Brooks said many important things. At the end of the presentation, however, I realized that Dr. Brooks never actually gave the definition of happiness. So, during the question and answer period, I asked him what his definition of human happiness is. He gave me a wry smile, made a few jokes about the difficulty of finding such an answer, and then answered the question in terms of Aristotle’s concept of eudaemonia and Thomas Aquinas’ explication of the idea (I’ll explain eudaemonism below). Of course, I perked up at his answer, and although the concept of eudaemonia is not new to me, Dr. Brooks helped me to think about it new ways.

As someone deeply interested in the nature of reality, I wondered if there was a connection between a correct understanding of reality, or being, and human happiness? So, after the lecture, I began to think about the connection between metaphysics, wisdom, and happiness, and what that might mean for human flourishing. What, if any, is the connection between metaphysics, the pursuit of wisdom, and happiness? What have the great philosophers said about the intersection of these topics and are they relevant to us in our own time and place? As a philosopher, I began to wonder—could a right understanding of reality promote and lay the intellectual groundwork for individual happiness and the betterment of society as a whole? If one were to have a better grasp of the truth of things and the world around them, would they then be able to live a more meaningful, significant, and purposeful life? How does one integrate these concepts? Fortunately for us, many excellent thinkers throughout history have said important things about the connection between philosophy, wisdom, and happiness. It will take some time, and many posts, but I hope to ultimately (and in various ways) make the connection between Aristotle’s definition of philosophy as the love wisdom, the importance of first principles, and human happiness. The following are some general thoughts and I hope to tie these ideas into my future posts as I explicate Aristotle’s conception of metaphysics as wisdom. What might happiness actually be and how is that tied to wisdom?

Happiness, like most other words, has different meanings and here we will focus on two of them. One is psychological or having to do with a state of mind or a pleasurable experience. This is the kind of contentment when one receives something desired. It is a pleasurable experience and often fleeting. Aristotle never denies that pleasurable experiences, if they are achieved in the right way and the right amount, have a certain kind of benefit to one’s well being. He also indicates that a certain amount of good fortune in life is helpful. But in each and every case, this kind of happiness is psychologically experiential, temporary, impermanent, and provisional. The other is based on what classical philosophers call eudaemonia or eudaemonism.

Eudemonia is the classical Greek word for happiness. Eudemonism is the study of the kind of happiness that is deeply significant and enduring. Although Plato had significant things to say about happiness, the concept of eudaemonia is attributed to Aristotle, since he was a strong advocate of the idea. Aristotle argued that the life of reason will lead to the best well balanced, meaningful, and happy life. He believes that thoughtful reflection and careful analysis will guide one to the most beneficial pleasures which will augment the balanced contemplative life. Eudaemonism, then, is the idea that the life of reason and careful analysis is the best path for happiness and self-fulfillment—it is human flourishing through the right use of reason. Also, remember, Aristotle was the great philosopher of balance and consonancy. For example, he was neither an ontological materialist nor a pure immaterialist as both belong together in the unity of life. There are harmony and agreement among the components of a well-lived life. He did not deny that a certain amount of life’s legitimate needs must be attained. Everyone needs food, clothing, shelter, etc. Nonetheless, eudaemonism teaches that the best approach to a meaningful existence also attends to the life of the mind and reason. Through reason, one can achieve the deepest and most long-lasting form of happiness because it attends to both the mind and body—not just the body alone.

Such a definition of happiness, then, as understood as eudaemonia, includes the moral and ethical dimension of life. Many philosophers speak about happiness as a life well lived. It refers to one’s whole life, a kind of deep and significant happiness which is the product of careful reasoning about life’s ultimate ends and then integration of virtue—the habit of right desire to achieve those ends. As the philosopher, Mortimer Adler explains, in this sense, it is not about an experience or something we can feel. It can be said that one is becoming happy or that one is on the path to happiness. Only when your life is over can someone else commenting on your life declare that you had lived a good life and can be described as a person who had achieved happiness. A happy life is a life which has a good ending. This is why wisdom teaches us to think carefully about the first principles of the world around us and what happiness means as the end, purpose, and final cause of our lives.