Metaphysics, Philosophy

Plato’s Metaphysical Answer to The One And The Many, Part Three.

Part one of this series can be found here.

Part two of this series can be found here.

Plato, however, does not simply divide reality into the transcendent world of Being and the physical world of Becoming. He further divides his two worlds in what has become known as the “divided line” in book six of the Republic.1 The divided line analogy not only seeks to provide a rational description of reality but also has epistemological implications. First, Plato gives this description:

Now take a line which has been cut into two unequal parts, and divide each of them again in the same proportion, and suppose the two main divisions to answer, one to the visible and the other to the intelligible, and then compare the subdivisions in respect of their clearness and want of clearness, and you will find that the first section in the sphere of the visible consists of images. And by images I mean, in the first place, shadows, and the second place, reflection in water and in solid, smooth and polished bodies and the like. (386 – 387)

In this part of book six of the Republic, Plato divides all reality into four sections, not two. Plato gives us a description of a line which itself attempts to divide metaphysics from epistemology. The line is then divided into four sections. This line still represents Plato’s hierarchy of reality but interestingly, he begins his presentation at the bottom of his hierarchy with the realm of images. Images such as shadows and reflections have the least degree of reality. The next section in the world of Becoming is the sensible objects of this world, which partake of a slightly stronger degree of reality. The next section divides Being from Becoming and is the section of mathematical Forms. Above the sections of mathematical Forms are the higher Forms. Plato, in this passage, does not define the “higher Forms,” but from a general reading of Plato, one would guess that he has the Forms of Goodness, Truth, or Justice in mind. All reality and knowledge is a hierarchy for Plato, and Plato has Socrates provide an epistemological understanding of his divided line:

You have quite conceived my meaning, I said; and now, corresponding to these four divisions, let there be four faculties in the soul – reason answering the highest, understanding to the second, faith (or conviction) to the third, and perception of shadows to the last – and let there be a scale of them, and let us suppose that the several faculties have clearness in the same degree that their subjects have truth. (387)

In this analogy and throughout various passages of Plato, Becoming epistemically corresponds to Opinion and Being to Knowledge. The realm of Opinion is divided into Imagination as the lowest and Perception as the higher category. In the transcendent world, Knowledge is divided into Reason as the lowest realm and Understanding as the ultimate. While Plato does not always explain how clearly divided these categories are to be, he does indicate that the realm of Being somehow emanates into the world of Becoming and somehow participates in it. In the Phaedo, Plato speaks of the Form as participating in the sensible world and the source of causation. In the Euthephro, however, Plato speaks as if sensible objects are copies or imitations of the Forms. In this way, Plato resolves the problem of the One and the Many. The Forms in the transcendent world (the One) emanate and participate in the world of Becoming (the Many).

The question remains, why was the problem of the one and the many so important to Plato? First, Plato understands that things that are Becoming cannot be their own causes; to become is to pass from non-Being to Being and non-Being cannot be a cause2. If non-Being cannot be a cause, Plato needs to find a source of change and cause in this world. Plato attempts to resolve this with his theory of Forms. The Forms participate in the world of Becoming and are the source of change and causation. As Socrates explains in the Euthephro, there must be some kind of standard to decide ethical decisions. Similarly, there must be some kind of standard for logical discourse if our thinking and discourse are to be meaningful. Plato posits the Forms as a kind of unchanging standard for meaningful discourse and ethical and moral actions. A world of only flux, change, and Becoming is a world of chaos. Furthermore, Plato also understands that the question of metaphysics is a basic one. How one views the world will determine how one views a variety of other things. If one believes the universe is simply governed by matter and mechanical causes, one could make a pretty good guess about what he or she believes about many other things. If, however, one believes in a transcendent standard of reality that is universal and unchanging, one could guess his or her understanding of things would be very different. In this way, metaphysics is a basic question and probably the reason why Socrates was so interested in examining the nature of reality and connecting it to ethics. For Plato, the transcendent realm of the Forms and their interaction with the world was his way of attempting to resolve these difficult philosophical matters.

As so often is the case in intellectual history, not everyone is convinced that Plato resolved the problem of the one and the many. Although most believe that his discovery of Form is very significant in one way or another. In our next post, I hope to explore how Aristotle, Plato’s greatest student, approached the problem of the one and the many and Aristotle’s contribution to metaphysics.

1 The divided line passage is too long to quote in its entirety, but I will summarize it here and point out the primary sections of his argument.

2 Plato explores this theme in the Timeaus and Parmenides among other places.

Works cited

Plato. The Dialogues of Plato. Trans. Benjamin Jowett. Great Books of the Western World. Vol. 6. Chicago: Encycyclopedia Britannica, Inc., 1996.

Metaphysics, Philosophy

Plato’s Metaphysical Answer to the One and the Many, Part Two

Part one of this series can be found here.

Plato attempts to resolve this question of the One and the Many with his theory of Forms. In order to understand how Plato discovers the transcendent world of the Forms, however, it is necessary to understand his categories of Being and Becoming. These categories are closely connected to the problem of the One and the Many. Basically, Plato’s conception of Being corresponds to the One and his category of Becoming corresponds to the Many. For Plato, Being must be one and unchanging. Being cannot involve multiplicity and change because that would include non-Being. That which is, cannot be that which is not. Due to the law of non-contradiction, Being cannot include non-Being. Plato’s category of Becoming (the Many) includes change and involves a mixture of multiplicity, change, and non-Being. If all reality involves the world of change, flux, and transformation – rationality, science, and thoughtful discourse would be impossible. Plato realized there had to be something that supported the basic nature of existence and provided a ground for understanding reality, logic, mathematics, and scientific inquiry. Plato conceived of this essential nature of reality as the transcendent and eternal realm of pure Being (the One). In his dialogue the Timeaeus, Plato describes his conception of Being and Becoming this way:

First then, in my judgment, we must make a distinction and ask, What is that which always is and has no becoming; and what is that which is always becoming and never is? That which is apprehended by intelligence and reason is always in the same state; but that which is conceived by opinion with the help of sensation and without reason, is always in a process of becoming and perishing and never really is. (447)

It is important to understand Plato’s dual worlds of Being and Becoming in order to fully grasp his metaphysical theory of Forms and to see how he resolved the question of the One and the Many. Plato’s theory of Forms states that every perishable and changing thing in the world of Becoming (the Many) is caused by a transcendent world (the One), which is populated by immutable, eternal Forms. Plato’s conception of transcendent reality is a world that lies beyond both space and time. In other words, according to Plato, every example of chair, human, instance of justice, or act of love has a perfect, unchangeable, transcendent Form that corresponds to it in the world of pure Being. In the Phaedo dialogue, Plato presents this passage which explains how sensible things participate in their transcendent Form:

I cannot help thinking, if there be anything beautiful other than absolute beauty should there be such, that it can be beautiful only in so far as it partakes of absolute beauty – and I should say the same of everything. Do you agree in this notion of the cause?

Yes, he said, I agree.

He proceeded: I know nothing and can understand nothing of any other of those wise causes which are alleged; and if a person says to me that the bloom of colour, or form or any such thing is a source of beauty, I leave all that, which is only confusing to me and simply and singly, and perhaps foolishly, hold and am assured in my own mind that nothing makes a thing beautiful but the presence and participation of beauty in whatever way or manner obtained. (242)

Tables not only participate or correspond to their perfect transcendent Form, but so do moral realities. In this way, Plato resolves the problem of the One and the Many. The Form existing in pure Being participates in the physical world of Becoming. Sometimes the Forms are referred to as Ideas because they can only be grasped through the intellect and human reason.

For Plato, the theory of the Forms and their interaction in the world of Becoming is not only true of the physical world, but also in the area of ethics in the attempt to discover what makes actions right or wrong. In the Euthyphro, Plato attempts to explore and describe how piety participates in the transcendent Form or Idea1 of piety:

Soc. Remember that I did not ask you to give me two or three examples of piety, but to explain the general idea which makes all pious things to be pious. Do you not recollect that there was one idea which made the impious impious and the pious pious?

Euth. I remember.

Soc. Tell me what is the nature of this idea, and then I shall have a standard to which I may look, and by which I may measure actions, whether yours or those of any one else, and then I shall be able to say that such and such an action is pious, such another impious. (193)

For Plato, not only do the things of becoming, things of this physical world, participate in an eternal Form, so do moral actions. In this way, Plato would tell us that the Bill of Rights (the first ten amendments of the United States Constitution) actually participates in the eternal and immutable Form of justice, although imperfectly. In the Republic, for example, Plato explains his project of attempting to define the big metaphysical idea of justice as a first step in discovering how it applies to particular individual instances of justice:

First let us complete the old investigation, which we began, as you remember, under the impression that, if we could previously examine justice on the larger scale, there would be less difficulty in discerning her in the individual. That larger example appeared to be the State, and accordingly we constructed as good a one as we could, knowing well that in the good State justice would be found. Let the discovery which we made be now applied to the individual. (350)

Metaphysically, Plato is interested in finding the perfect model of justice and then trying to figure out how that model or idea of justice works out at the particular level. In part three, we will discover how Plato further divides reality. Then we will evaluate whether or not Plato was successful in his attempt to resolve the problem of the one and the many.

Works cited

Plato. The Dialogues of Plato. Trans. Benjamin Jowett. Great Books of the Western World. Vol. 6. Chicago: Encycyclopedia Britannica, Inc., 1996.

1 The Greek word ‘eidos’ can mean both Form and Idea.

Metaphysics, Philosophy

Aristotle on “True Truth”

I will get to my explication of Plato soon. In the meantime, I wanted to share one of the most beautiful and inspiring philosophical passages of the Western intellectual tradition. Perhaps I will write about it sometime. Right now, however, I do not want to say anything about it for fear of ruining it. Just enjoy.

It is right also that philosophy should be called knowledge of the truth. For the end of theoretical knowledge is truth, while that of practical knowledge is action (for even if they consider how things are, practical men do not study the eternal, but what is relative and in the present). Now we do not know a truth without its cause; and a thing has a a quality in a higher degree than other things if in virtue of it the similar quality belongs to the other things as well (e.g. fire is the hottest of things; for it is the cause of the heat of all other things); so that that which causes derivative truths to be true is most true. Hence the principles of eternal things must be always most true (for they are not merely sometimes true, nor is there any cause of their being, but they themselves are the cause of the being of other things), so that as each thing is in respect of being, so is it in respect of truth. (Aristotle, Metaphysics, Book II, end of chapter 1)

Metaphysics, Philosophy

Plato’s Metaphysical Answer to the One and the Many, Part One

Our philosophical reflection on the question of the one and the many brings us to the ancient Greek philosopher Plato (427 – 347 B.C). Plato is arguably the most influential philosopher in Western intellectual history and is most known for his theory of transcendent forms (Ideas or essences). Plato held that these transcendent forms are imperfectly mirrored in the sensible world and known through the intellect alone. Ideas, according to Plato, are the highest order of reality while matter is subject to the formative effects of the Ideas. We will get to the rest of Plato’s philosophy a little later. For now, we need to think about the importance of metaphysics in the first place, the question of the one and the many, and how Plato came to the discovery of Form or Idea. This will be the first post of three which will explore Plato’s attempt to resolve the metaphysical question of the one and the many.

Metaphysics is the study of the reality in which we find ourselves and the transcendent reality that makes this world possible. Sometimes philosophers define metaphysics as the study of ultimate reality. Of course, the study of ultimate reality generates many questions. Some of these questions include: How is reality connected to being and existence? What is the essential nature to being or the totality of all that exists? Is reality one or many? If it is many, how does it relate to the one? In fact, it is this question—the question or problem known as “the One and the Many” that puzzled Plato and ultimately caused him to formulate his metaphysical conception of Form. The problem of the One and the Many, is also related to questions of Universal and Particular and Being and Becoming. Plato was certainly perplexed by the question of the One and the Many, the idea of Being and Becoming, and through his investigation of these questions, he became the first systematic metaphysician. He also realized that in some way, metaphysics was basic to all other philosophical concerns.

With this foundation, it is important to understand Plato’s place in Western intellectual history as the foremost systematic philosopher. Although there were others before him, commonly known as the pre-Socratics, who explored interesting metaphysical theories regarding the nature of reality, Plato was the first to describe reality in a methodical and rationally compelling way1. The pre-Socratics, however, asked some fundamental questions about reality that perplexed Plato and influenced his metaphysical outlook. The pre-Socratics, for example, wondered what could be the essential nature of all things and how this essential nature relates to everything else. This question has come down to us as the problem of the One and the Many. The question of the One and the Many is an attempt to intellectually explore the structure of reality. It seeks to find unifying principles in the diversity around us. In other words, the question of the One and the Many is an attempt to make sense out of the world. From Plato’s perspective, the question explores the unities of goodness, justice, or the nature geometry and mathematics, and then tries to explain how these unities, which do not change, exist as diverse particularities in the world. This basic philosophical puzzle has to do with the nature of change and causation. The pre-Socratics, and Plato, were aware that many things change from one thing to another. After all, change is all around us – life, death, seasons, and time itself all are indications of change.

Plato was keenly aware of the problem of the One and the Many. In the Philebus, for example, Socrates says, “The principle which has just turned up, which is a marvel of nature; for that one should be many or many one, are wonderful propositions” (Plato 611). Later, Socrates explains:

A gift of heaven, which, as I conceive, the gods tossed among men by the hands of a new Prometheus, and therewith a blaze of light; and the ancients, who were our betters and nearer the gods than we are, handed down the tradition, that whatever things are said to be are composed of one and many, and have the finite and the infinite implanted in them: seeing then that such is the order of the world, we too ought in every enquiry to begin by laying down one idea of that which is the subject of inquiry; this unity we shall find in everything. (Plato 612)

The question of the one and the many is an attempt to discover the essential nature upon which everything else depends for its existence. The intuition to reduce reality to its essential nature is significant. Scientific theories that unite and make sense out of many other theories and concepts are generally accepted and considered superior models of explanation. It seems basic to human nature to take simplicity and unity as having explanatory power2. There is a rational human impulse to seek and discover a unity or system of thought that provides an answer for everything else related to it. The same is true for those who seek a foundation for reality. Even amidst change, things are interdependent. The question of the One and the Many provides a way to explore and discuss that which everything else depends on for existence. Plato brings this notion to light when he has Socrates discuss the nature of virtue in the Meno dialogue:

How fortunate I am, Meno! When I ask you for one virtue, you present me with a swarm of them, which are in your keeping. Suppose that I carry on the figure of the swarm, and ask of you, What is the nature of the bee? And you answer that there are many kinds of bees, because there are many and different kinds of them; or are they not rather to be distinguished by some other quality, as for example beauty, size, or shape? (Plato 175)

In this example, Socrates is investigating the nature of virtue by way of natural philosophy. Plato has Socrates explain that just as moral acts have the potential of reflecting the true nature of virtue, there is something in nature, as well, that can reflect the essential character or “Being” of the physical world. The One and the Many has interesting political ramifications too. In the political world, the great American experiment is an attempt to unite the many. For example, the motto on the Seal of the United States says “E Pluribus Unum” – from the many, one – in an attempt to describe the American ethos of bringing unity out of the diversity of the many. Not only politically, however, but in the physical world, the tension of the One and the Many holds true as well. In part two, we will discover how Plato attempts to resolve this question and why it is important for Western intellectual history and the implications for us today.

Plato. The Dialogues of Plato. Trans. Benjamin Jowett. Great Books of the Western World. Vol. 6. Chicago: Encycyclopedia Britannica, Inc., 1996.

1 On occasion, Plato references the pre-Socratic thinker Heraclitus. Plato was certainly aware of and in discussion with the ideas that came before him and was also influenced by Parmenides.

2 This is why many metaphysicians use Occam’s razor to decide among competing theories of reality.