“Let us call to our aid those who have attacked the investigation of being and philosophized about reality before us.” – Aristotle, Metaphysics, I, 3.
Being is the
fundamental object of study for the metaphysician. In this essay, I
will outline why the study of Being as Being is foundational, and
perhaps the most basic to all other issues related to philosophy.
This is not a purely academic question or one that is the sole
concern of philosophers. As the Canadian philosopher George Grant
reminds us, all civilizations have paradigms of knowledge and such
paradigms dramatically shape every part of the society (36). The way
we think about the ultimate issues and conditions of reality impacts
the way we think and interact with each other in society. I have
become convinced that the more I study the nature of Being, the more
connections I find at the human level of technology, economics, law,
and education.
To start, Being includes all reality including physical nature, conceptual abstractions, essences, and potentialities. In Aristotelian and Thomist terms, Being incorporates all that which is in act and potential, being and essence. The concepts of essence, act, and potency are the most helpful and importat for understanding reality. Philosophers from the time of Heraclitus to Martin Heidegger have tried to unlock the mystery of Being because it is believed that understanding Being leads one to what it means to be and become in this world. When one makes sense of Being, it is easier to make helpful judgments about reality, whether it is one or many, completely fluid or essentially static, ordered or chaotic, and good or bad, or perhaps both. If the world is essentially chaotic, as Heraclitus believed, how does one live meaningfully and “become” in such a world? Being includes both being and becoming, essences, values, and change and how one answers these questions have important implications for human life and activity. These questions are foundational to human flourishing. The philosopher Immanuel Kant (1724–1804) believed that these kinds of metaphysical questions are unavoidable. He tells us in the preface to the first edition of his Critique of Pure Reason:
For it is in reality vain to profess indifference in regard to such inquiries, the object of which cannot be indifferent to humanity. Besides, these pretended indifferentists, however much they may try to disguise themselves by the assumption of a popular style and by changes on the language of the schools, unavoidably fall into metaphysical declarations and propositions, which they profess to regard with so much contempt. (1, italics in original)
It is true that in
today’s intellectual climate, Being is thought to be unimportant or
impossible to figure out. But have you ever heard someone—perhaps
Kant would call an indifferentist—turn around and give her
explanation for doing something based on her understanding of
reality? If someone were to tell you that all reality is simple
matter and mechanics, you would have a good idea of what she thinks
on other important issues. Metaphysical questions are unavoidable
and everyone seems to have something to say about these ultimate
matters even when they claim they are indifferent or agnostic to
them. Our understanding of reality shapes many other things in our
lives. The question is, “are we going to have a well-developed
notion of Being or not”?
One way to evaluate a philosophy or particular philosopher is to examine how the concept of Being is handled. Does the philosophy illuminate and help us to understand the nature of Being or is the issue sidestepped or simply untouched? Does the philosophy help us to understand the nature of existence a little more or does the philosophy or philosopher think the attempt is futile? These are the questions we are going to keep in mind as we explore the philosophical assumptions of Rene Descartes in regards to his conception of Being. This time, however, we will use Kant and Aristotle as helpful guides.
Descartes was an interesting and important philosopher who contributed much to the rational approach to philosophy. And he really did not have that much to say about Being as Being in the way Aristotle did. Descartes’ main project was to prove the existence of God and the immortality of the human soul. Since he was very skeptical of the fundamental principles of Being—act, potency, essences, and most of causation—he ended up painting himself into a corner, and the only way he could describe physical reality was by way of mechanism. In this aspect of his thought, he really is close to Francis Bacon and Thomas Hobbes. When it comes to physical reality all we need to do is “render ourselves masters and possessors of nature” (285). (Along with Bacon and Hobbes, Descartes was very triumphant about the scientific “new method” and mankind’s newfound destiny to master nature. Today many philosophers of technology are exploring the question of whether or not something should be done simply because it can be done.) Descartes was very clear in his Meditations on First Philosophy that he was indifferent to matters of metaphysics or the claims of ultimate reality. If the issue was not immediately clear, certain, and indubitable, he would reject it. Of course, Descartes’ metaphysical skepticism was based on theological grounds because he did not want to assume the purposes or mind of God regarding nature. Nonetheless, his interpretive scheme has consequences. Metaphysics, according to Descartes is seen as doubtful. And those following Descartes believed that the project of laying out the first principles of reality was a worthless task.
This, however, brings us again to the philosopher Immanuel Kant. Kant’s entire project in his Critique of Pure Reason was to revive the corpse of metaphysics. He took upon the task of reviving metaphysics when in his day most scholars believed such a project was pointless. He reminds us,
Yet in a certain sense, this kind of knowledge must unquestionably be looked upon as given; in other words, metaphysics must be considered as really existing, if not as a science, nevertheless as a natural disposition of the human mind (metaphysica naturalis). For human reason, without any instigations imputable to the mere vanity of great knowledge, unceasingly progresses, urged on by its own feeling of need, towards such questions as cannot be answered by any empirical application of reason, or principles derived therefrom; and so there has ever really existed in every man some system of metaphysics. It will always exist, so soon as reason awakes to the exercise of its power of speculation. (19)
For Kant,
metaphysics is an innate natural disposition of every human being.
It is unavoidable. It would be impossible to go into all of Kant’s
philosophy at this point. But in summary, much of Kant’s thought
highlights the importance of basic laws and principles that must be
in place to render anything intelligible, including metaphysical
knowledge. Aristotle says much the same thing in his Posterior
Analytics and Analytics (and, of course, was the first philosopher to
elucidate the human need to understand the first principles of
reality in his Metaphysics). The philosopher Daniel Sullivan reminds
us that, “our most commonplace expressions of optimism or
pessimism, selfishness or high-mindedness, idealism or cynicism,
carry along with them unacknowledged assumptions about the nature of
the universe as a whole and man’s place in it” (7). Why does
metaphysics matter? Because in unpredictable ways, an understanding
of reality is assumed in the conversations we have, the books we
read, the movies we watch and the political associations we keep.
All these, and more imply a philosophy or perspective on reality and
life.
Works Cited
Descartes, Rene.
Bacon, Descartes, Spinoza. Great Books of the Western World. Vol. 28.
Encyclopedia Britannica, Inc., 1999.
Grant, George.
Technology & Justice. House of Anansi Press, 1986.
Kant, Immanuel. The
Critique of Pure Reason, The Critique of Practical Reason and Other
Ethical Treatises, The Critique of Judgement. Great Books of the
Western World. Vol. 39. Encyclopedia Britannica, Inc., 1999.
Sullivan, Daniel J.
An Introduction to Philosophy: Perennial Principles of the Classical
Realist Tradition. Tan Books, 1957.
Recent Comments